The Kalam Cosmological Argument commits the fallacy of equivocation (twice!)
I've dished out some critiques of William Lane Craig's Kalam Cosmological Argument (well... he didn't make it up, but he's certainly popularized it) recently – here, and more recently here. But today I thought of another angle to approach refuting this argument, and even though I don't want this to turn into Mike D's Official Kalam Criticism Blog, I thought it was worth sharing. I should point out that I'm certainly not the first person to have thought of the basic concepts here, but I'm hoping this will nicely supplement my previous arguments in addition to standing on its own.
The fallacy of equivocation is when you use a word that has multiple meanings, but you're not clear on which meaning of the word your argument is using. The Kalam is actually a fine example, because it commits this fallacy twice, and in doing so commits the fallacy of assuming the consequent, which is when you assume the conclusion – either whole or in part – in one of the premises. A refresh on the Kalam:
But wait!
There's another fallacy of equivocation, and that is the use of the word cause. William Lane Craig himself makes a distinction between two types of causality – "temporal" causality, which is the physical causality we observe within the universe, and (obviously) "non-temporal" causality, which is the kind of causality that exists a priori to our universe and caused our universe to come into temporal (physical) existence. But the existence of non-temporal causality is precisely what the Kalam is trying to establish. So to avoid assuming the consequent, the first premise must strictly be referring to temporal causality. So a really accurate phrasing of the first premise would be:
The Kalam commits the fallacy of equivocation two times and assumes the consequent, therefor it's an invalid argument. And to think, William Lane Craig wrote a whole book on it. What a shame.
The fallacy of equivocation is when you use a word that has multiple meanings, but you're not clear on which meaning of the word your argument is using. The Kalam is actually a fine example, because it commits this fallacy twice, and in doing so commits the fallacy of assuming the consequent, which is when you assume the conclusion – either whole or in part – in one of the premises. A refresh on the Kalam:
- Everything that begins to exist has a cause
- The universe began to exist
- Ergo, the universe has a cause
- All physical things in our universe that begin to exist have a cause
But wait!
There's another fallacy of equivocation, and that is the use of the word cause. William Lane Craig himself makes a distinction between two types of causality – "temporal" causality, which is the physical causality we observe within the universe, and (obviously) "non-temporal" causality, which is the kind of causality that exists a priori to our universe and caused our universe to come into temporal (physical) existence. But the existence of non-temporal causality is precisely what the Kalam is trying to establish. So to avoid assuming the consequent, the first premise must strictly be referring to temporal causality. So a really accurate phrasing of the first premise would be:
- All physical things in our universe that begin to exist have a temporal (physical) cause
- All physical things in our universe that begin to exist have a temporal (physical) cause
- The universe itself began to exist
- Ergo, the universe has a non-temporal cause
The Kalam commits the fallacy of equivocation two times and assumes the consequent, therefor it's an invalid argument. And to think, William Lane Craig wrote a whole book on it. What a shame.
Comments
Post a Comment